The Relationship between the Topological Properties and Common Modal Logics
1Department of Mathematics, California State University, Fresno
Abstract
A modal language is the language of the classical logic extended by additional operator(s), e.g. . Modal logics have a variety of interpretations and applications in different sciences, and depending on the context, different axioms involving
may be assumed. In topological interpretations, the operator
interpreted as interior. It is well known that the modal logic S4 is sound and complete over all topological spaces. In this paper we reverse the question. Given a set X and any interpretation of
in X that satisfies a given subset of the axioms of S4, we determine which topological properties must be possessed by the image of the interpretation of
.
Keywords: modal logic, topological space
Copyright © 2016 Science and Education Publishing. All Rights Reserved.Cite this article:
- Maria Nogin, Bing Xu. The Relationship between the Topological Properties and Common Modal Logics. Journal of Mathematical Sciences and Applications. Vol. 4, No. 1, 2016, pp 29-33. https://pubs.sciepub.com/jmsa/4/1/5
- Nogin, Maria, and Bing Xu. "The Relationship between the Topological Properties and Common Modal Logics." Journal of Mathematical Sciences and Applications 4.1 (2016): 29-33.
- Nogin, M. , & Xu, B. (2016). The Relationship between the Topological Properties and Common Modal Logics. Journal of Mathematical Sciences and Applications, 4(1), 29-33.
- Nogin, Maria, and Bing Xu. "The Relationship between the Topological Properties and Common Modal Logics." Journal of Mathematical Sciences and Applications 4, no. 1 (2016): 29-33.
Import into BibTeX | Import into EndNote | Import into RefMan | Import into RefWorks |
1. Introduction: Modal Logic Language and Its Interpretation in Topological Spaces
Definition 1.1. Let be a modal language consisting of propositional variables, conjunction
, disjunction
negation
, and modality
Implication
and biconditional
are defined in the traditional way (
and
). Modality
is defined as the dual to
, i.e.
Modal logics have a variety of interpretations and applications in difference sciences, from philosophy to computer science. Depending on the context and interpretation of , its different properties may be desired. Some of the most meaningful, useful, and studied axioms are listed below.
Adding the Necessitation Rule and some of the above axioms to any axiom system of the classical propotional logic, we get the axiom systems for some common modal logics:
Definition 1.2. A topological model of is a pair
, where
1. is a topological space, and
2. is a function mapping formulas in
to subsets of
. It assigns each propositional variable
an arbitrary subset
and satisfies the following conditions for every
:
![]() |
3. where is the topological interior operator.
Remark 1.3. Note that the modality then maps to the topological closure operator, i.e.
Definition 1.4. Let be any formula. We say that
is valid in a topological space
if for any topological model
, we have
.
Theorem 1.5. (Topological completeness of S4, [3, 4, 5, 6, 7]) For any formula , the following two statements are equivalent:
• is derivable in S4;
• is valid in all topological spaces.
In the rest of this paper, we will study this topic from a different direction: given any set and any interpretation of
in
that satisfies S4 (this concept is defined in the next section), we show that the image of this interpretation is a topology on
. Moreover, in section 2 we summarize the influence of the modal axioms of S4 on topological properties of the image. Proofs are given in section 3.
2. The Relationship between the Topological Properties and Common Modal Logics
Suppose we are given a set and a mapping
, where
is the power set of
and
. For any mapping
is a propositional variable}
and any formulas
and
, define
![]() |
We say that a formula is valid in
if for every such mapping
,
. We say that a mapping
satisfies a modal logic L, or equivalently, makes L sound, if all formulas derivable in L are valid in
.
Suppose that such a mapping makes S4 sound. We ask the following questions. Is the set
a topology of
? If so, does
have to satisfy all axioms of S4 to guarantee that
is a topology of
? We show that the answers to both questions above are “yes". If any axiom of S4 is dropped, then
is not necessarily a topology. Moreover, we determine which axioms of modal logic are responsible for which axioms of the topological spaces. More precisely, Table 3 below shows which axioms of topology,
•
•
•
•
the set has when i satisfies the axiom system of logic L, where L is one of the following:
(1)
(2) plus Axioms
and 4,
(3) K,
(4) K4,
(5) D,
(6) D4,
(7) T,
(8) S4,
(9) S5.
In this table, the symbol "×" means that does not have to have the property with the assigned logic, and "√" means it does. Of course, unless we put some interpretation on
,
can be any mapping, so we can not expect it to have any topological properties. However, as we see (in cell 1A), requiring as little as the Necessitation Rule already guarantees one of the properties.
Observe that no proper sublogic of S4 guarantees that is a topology. Also observe that Axiom D is weaker than Axiom
, but logic D guarantees the same properties as logic T. It is also interesting that adding Axiom 4 to K or D (and obtaining K4 or D4, respectively) does not add any topological property, but adding Axiom 4 to T (and obtaining S4) does.
3. Proofs
The following two lemmas are proved e.g. in [[2], p.69] and [[1],p. 38].
Lemma 3.1. The formula is derivable in logic K.
Lemma 3.2. Axiom D follows from Axiom T.
Lemma 3.3. If Axiom is satisfied, then i is an increasing mapping.
Proof. Let We will show that
Let
and
for some interpretation
and formulas
and
Then
![]() |
Lemma 3.4. Let satisfy logic S4. If
then
Proof. First we will show that Let
for some interpretation
and formula
Since
it follows that
For the other direction, since
there exists
such that
Now let
for some interpretation
and formula
Then
![]() |
Therefore,
Proposition 3.5. Column A in Table 3. The property holds for any set X and any mapping
that satisfies the axiom system of the logic L, where
plus Axioms T, 4, K, K4, D, D4, T, S4, or S5.
Proof. It is sufficient to prove this is true for because it is a sublogic of all the other logics. We will show that
Let
be any formula derivable in this logic. Then
for any interpretation
By the Necessitation Rule,
is valid. Therefore,
Proposition 3.6. Results B1, B3, and B4 in Table 3. Let be a nonempty set. Then there exists a mapping
such that i satisfies logic L, where
K, or K4, however,
Proof. Define for any
In this case,
and thus the property
does not hold. However, as we will show below, this mapping
satisfies the Necessitation Rule, Axiom
, and Axiom 4.
It satisfies the Necessitation Rule (if then
) because for any formula F such that
we have
Axiom is valid in
because for any formulas
and for any interpretation
![]() |
Axiom 4 is valid in
because for any formula
and any interpretation
![]() |
Proposition 3.7. Results B2, B5, B6, B7, B8, and B9 in Table 3. If satisfies the axiom system of logic L, where
plus Axioms 4,
D, D4, T, S4, or S5, then
Proof. Since each logic in the proposition includes and Axiom
it is sufficient to show the case when i satisfies
plus Axiom
Suppose that
satisfies
plus Axiom
Let
be a contradiction in the classical logic, e.g.
Then
for any interpretation
So
![]() |
Therefore,
Proposition 3.8. Results C1 and C2 in Table 3. There exists a set and a mapping
that satisfies
or
plus Axioms T and 4, but the property
does not hold.
Proof. Consider the set and the mapping i such that
![]() |
The mapping satisfies the necessitation rule because if
then
It satisfies Axiom 4 because for any subset
of
such that
we have
and for
It satisfies Axiom
because
for any
However, the property
does not hold because
Proposition 3.9. Results C3, C4, C5, C6, C7, C8, and C9 in Table 3. The property holds for any mapping
that satisfies logic K, K4, D, T, ,D4, S4, or S5.
Proof. It is sufficient to prove this is true for logic K because it is a sublogic of all the other listed logics. Let Then
for some
Let
and
for some interpretation
and formulas
and
Then
![]() |
Proposition 3.10. Results D1, D2, D3, D4, D5, D6, and D7 in Table 3. There exists a set and a mapping
that satisfies logic L (where
plus Axioms
K, K4, D, T, or D4), but the property
does not hold for the set
Proof. Results D1 and D2: or
plus Axioms
Consider and the mapping
such that
![]() |
The mapping satisfies the necessitation rule because if
for some formula F, then
It satisfies Axiom
because
for any
Finally, it satisfies Axiom 4 because
for any
The union property does not hold because
Results D3, D4, D5, and D6: L= K, K4, D, or D4.
Consider the set and the mapping i such that
![]() |
Then
(i) Axiom is valid in
since, as we will see below,
![]() |
Case 1: Then
![]() |
for any
Case 2: Then
![]() |
for any
Case 3: We need to show that
for any
If
or
then
![]() |
If
or
then
![]() |
Case 4: The proof in this case can be obtained from that in Case 3 by switching
and
Case 5: . Then
![]() |
Case 6: Then
![]() |
Case 7: We will show that
for any
If
or
then
![]() |
If
, or
then
![]() |
Case 8: The proof in this case can be obtained from that in Case 7 by switching
and
(ii) Axiom 4 is valid in because
for any
(iii) Axiom is valid. Indeed, we know that Axiom
is satisfied. So we have
for all
Therefore, for all
we have
which is equivalent to
(iv) The union property does not hold because
![]() |
Result D7: L= T.
Consider the set and the mapping i such that
![]() |
(i) Axiom is valid in
namely,
for any
Case 1: Then
![]() |
for any
Case 2: is a subset of
such that
Then
![]() |
for any
Case 3: or
or
. Without loss of generality, let
We need to show that
If then
If then
If or
then
![]() |
If or
then
![]() |
If then
If then
(ii) Axiom is valid in
since for all
(iii) The union property does not hold because
![]() |
Proposition 3.11. Results D8 and D9 in Table 3. If satisfies logic S4 or S5, then the property
holds for the set
Proof. It is sufficient to prove this is true for logic S4 because it is a sublogic of logic S5. Let By Lemma 4, we have
![]() |
for each Then
![]() |
By Axiom we have
![]() |
Therefore,
![]() |
Acknowledgments
Both authors would like to thank the College of Science and Mathematics of the California State University, Fresno for supporting this work.
References
[1] | W. Carnielli and C. Pizzi. Modalities and multimodalities. Springer, 2008. | ||
![]() | View Article | ||
[2] | M. Fitting and R. L. Mendelsohn. First-order modal logic. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Boston, 1998. | ||
![]() | View Article | ||
[3] | J. C. C. McKinsey and A. Tarski. The algebra of topology, Ann. of Math.(2) 45 (1944) 141-191. | ||
![]() | View Article | ||
[4] | G. Mints. A completeness proof for propositional S4 in cantor space, in: E. Orlowska (Ed.), Logic at Work: Essays Dedicated to the Memory of Helena Rasiowa, Physica-Verlag, Heidelberg, 1998. | ||
![]() | PubMed | ||
[5] | G. Mints, T. Zhang. A proof of topological completeness of S4 in (0,1), Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 133 (2005) 231-245. | ||
![]() | View Article | ||
[6] | M. Aiello, J. van Bentehm, G. Bezhanishvili. Reasoning about space: the modal way, J. Logic Comput. 13(6) (2003) 889-920. | ||
![]() | View Article | ||
[7] | G. Bezhanishvili and M. Gehrke. Completeness of S4 with respect to the real line: revisited, Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 131 (2005) 287-301. | ||
![]() | View Article | ||